The Eckmann–Hilton Argument

Published

As promised, this post is about the famous Eckmann–Hilton argument. This argument, on the surface, looks like a simple algebraic trick; but it has deep consequences, which I will now try to explain. This post is an expanded version of a math.SE answer I wrote some time ago.

Some background

When I was a first-year student at the ENS, we had to write a “Mémoire de première année” (“First-year essay”) on a topic. I wrote mine together with Maxence Novel, with Grégory Ginot as advisor, about the Eckmann–Hilton argument. You can find it here (it’s in French; bear in mind that we were undergrads when we wrote this).

This was my first exposure to many topics: algebraic topology, operads, ∞-categories… And it definitely shaped up my current mathematical interests. I still remember trying to read Lurie’s Higher Algebra armed only with point-set topology and basic category theory! Needless to say I didn’t get very far. I very much enjoyed the experience anyway.

The argument

Without further ado, here is the theorem:

Theorem (Eckmann–Hilton argument). Let MM be a set equipped with two monoid structures (M,)(M,*) and (M,)(M, \cdot) sharing the same unit 1M1 \in M. Assume that they satisfy the interchange law:

(ab)(cd)=(ac)(bd).(a \cdot b) * (c \cdot d) = (a * c) \cdot (b * d).

Then both structures are equal (ab=aba * b = a \cdot b) and moreover they are commutative (ab=baa * b = b * a).

Basically, what this means is that if you have a set with two “compatible” laws on it, then they are equal and commutative. It’s rather powerful. This theorem can be further refined: you don’t need to assume that both laws have the same unit, and you don’t even have to assume that they are commutative. It all follows from the interchange law. But for the sack of simplicity I’ll stick with these assumptions.

The proof is amazingly concise:

ab=(a1)(1b)=(a1)(1b)ab=ab=(1a)(b1)=(1b)(a1)ab=ba.\begin{align*} a * b & = (a \cdot 1) * (1 \cdot b) \\ & = (a * 1) \cdot (1 * b) \\ a * b & = a \cdot b \\ & = (1 * a) \cdot (b * 1) \\ & = (1 \cdot b) * (a \cdot 1) \\ a * b & = b * a. \end{align*}

Pretty nifty!

Interpretation

One can reformulate the interchange law: it is equivalent to the fact that :(M,)2(M,)* : (M, \cdot)^2 \to (M, \cdot) is a morphism of monoids, and also equivalently, :(M,)2(M,)\cdot : (M, *)^2 \to (M, *) is a morphism of monoids. Thus we get a reformulation of the Eckmann–Hilton argument (sorry folks, this blog will contain a lot of category theory):

Reformulation. A monoid object in the category of monoids is an abelian monoid.

Reformulated in this way, the argument immediately generalizes. Let (C,)(\mathsf{C}, \otimes) be a monoidal category. The category Mon(C)\mathsf{Mon}(\mathsf{C}) is the category of monoid objects in C\mathsf{C}: its objects are triplet (M,μ,η)(M, \mu, \eta), where MM is an object of C\mathsf{C}, μ:M2M\mu : M^2 \to M and η:1CM\eta : 1_{\mathsf{C}} \to M satisfy the axioms of a monoid (associativity, unitality).

If C\mathsf{C} is symmetric monoidal, then Mon(C)\mathsf{Mon}(C) can be equipped with a tensor product. If (M,μ,η)(M, \mu, \eta) and (M,μ,η)(M', \mu', \eta') are two monoids, their tensor product is defined to be (MM,μ~,ηη)(M \otimes M', \tilde{\mu}, \eta \otimes \eta'), where μ~\tilde{\mu} is the composite (I’m forgetting about associativity constraints):

MMMMMMMMμμMM.M \otimes M' \otimes M \otimes M' \cong M \otimes M \otimes M' \otimes M' \xrightarrow{\mu \otimes \mu'} M \otimes M'.

So one can speak about monoid objects inside Mon(CC)\mathsf{Mon}(\mathsf{CC}). Then the Eckmann–Hilton argument says:

Theorem. Let (C,)(\mathsf{C}, \otimes) be a symmetric monoidal category. Then the category of monoid objects in Mon(C)\mathsf{Mon}(\mathsf{C}) is equivalent to the category Monab(C)\mathsf{Mon}_{ab}(\mathsf{C}) of abelian monoids in C\mathsf{C}.

The proof is exactly the same as before, except that you need to translate it into commutative diagrams.

First applications

Fundamental groups of H-spaces

An H-space is a space XX equipped with a “multiplication” μ:X2X\mu : X^2 \to X which is unital up to homotopy: there exists eXe \in X such that both μ(e,)\mu(e, -) and μ(,e)\mu(-,e) are homotopic to the identity of XX. Topological monoids are examples of H-spaces.

Then the Eckmann–Hilton argument can be used to show that the fundamental group π1(X,e)\pi_1(X,e) is commutative. Indeed, this fundamental group has two multiplications: the usual concatenation of loops *, and the multiplication of loops \cdot induced by μ\mu, given by:

(γγ)(t)=μ(γ(t),γ(t)).(\gamma \cdot \gamma')(t) = \mu(\gamma(t), \gamma'(t)).

These two laws are unital (the unit being the class of the constant loop equal to ee), and they are compatible in the sense of Eckmann–Hilton. It thus follows:

  1. That these laws are equal, meaning that the concatenation of two loops is homotopic to their product with μ\mu;
  2. And commutative, meaning that the concatenation of two loops is homotopic to their concatenation in the reverse order!

This has immediate consequences: a space like S1S1S^1 \vee S^1 with a nonabelian fundamental group cannot be given an H-space structure.

Higher homotopy groups

This section can be summarized by this picture:

Homotopy between fg and gf

It is a depiction of the Eckmann–Hilton argument applied to π2(X)\pi_2(X). To understand it, consider a set MM with two monoid structures; instead of writing them with two different operators, represent one of them with horizontal multiplication and the other with vertical multiplication, like this:

ab=(ab),ab=(ba).a * b = \begin{pmatrix} a & b \end{pmatrix}, \qquad a \cdot b = \begin{pmatrix} b \\ a \end{pmatrix}.

The interchange law then exactly says that this multiplication is not ambiguous:

(cdab)\begin{pmatrix} c & d \\ a & b \end{pmatrix}

One can either multiply first each line horizontally and then vertically to get (ab)(cd)(a * b) \cdot (c * d), or first each column vertically and then horizontally to get (ac)(bd)(a \cdot c) * (b \cdot d), and both are equal by the interchange law. The proof of the Eckmann–Hilton argument then goes like this:

(ab)=(1ba1)=(ba)=(b11a)=(ba)\begin{align} \begin{pmatrix} a & b \end{pmatrix} & = \begin{pmatrix} 1 & b \\ a & 1 \end{pmatrix} \\ & = \begin{pmatrix} b \\ a \end{pmatrix} \\ & = \begin{pmatrix} b & 1 \\ 1 & a \end{pmatrix} \\ & = \begin{pmatrix} b & a \end{pmatrix} \end{align}

This is very similar to the picture at the beginning of the section! To understand it, recall that the second fundamental group π2(X,e)\pi_2(X,e) can be defined as the set:

π2(X,e)={γ:[0,1]2Xγ([0,1]2)={x0}}/\pi_2(X,e) = \{ \gamma : [0,1]^2 \to X \mid \gamma(\partial [0,1]^2) = \{ x_0 \} \} / \sim

quotiented out by homotopy of maps. Since the square [0,1]2[0,1]^2 is two-dimensional, π2(X,e)\pi_2(X,e) has two composition laws: concatenation in the horizontal direction, and concatenation in the vertical direction. Both are associative, and they satisfy the interchange law (the reader is advised to draw a picture), so by the Eckmann–Hilton argument, both are equal and commutative! And the proof looks just like the picture at the beginning of the section.

Remark. This can be deduced from the fact that the fundamental group of an H-space is abelian. Indeed, π2(X)π1(ΩX)\pi_2(X) \cong \pi_1(\Omega X), where ΩX\Omega X is the loop space of XX; since ΩX\Omega X is an H-space (by concatenation of loops), then its fundamental group is abelian. By induction πn(X)\pi_n(X) is abelian for all nn.

Monoids and comonoids

Let C\mathsf{C} be a cartesian closed category. A comonoid in C\mathsf{C} is a monoid in the opposite category Cop\mathsf{C}^{op}, equipped with the tensor product given by the categorical coproduct. More explicitly, it’s an object XX equipped with a “comultiplication” Δ:XXX\Delta : X \to X \sqcup X and a “counit” ϵ:X\epsilon : X \to * satisfying axioms formally dual to that a of a monoid.

Then if MM is a monoid in C\mathsf{C} (with respect to the tensor product given by the categorical product), the hom-set homC(X,M)\hom_{\mathsf{C}}(X,M) is equipped with two different multiplications: given f,g:XMf,g : X \to M, one can either consider fg:XMf*g : X \to M given by XΔXXfgMX \xrightarrow{\Delta} X \sqcup X \xrightarrow{f \sqcup g} M, or fgf \cdot g given by X(f,g)M×MμMX \xrightarrow{(f,g)} M \times M \xrightarrow{\mu} M. One can then check that both are compatible in the sense of Eckmann–Hilton, thus homC(X,M)\hom_{\mathsf{C}}(X,M) is a commutative monoid.

This is a generalization of the fact about the fundamental groups: let C=Top\mathsf{C} = \mathsf{Top}_* be the category of pointed topological spaces. Then S1S^1, equipped with the “pinch map” S1S1S1S^1 \to S^1 \vee S^1 that collapses two points, is a comonoid up to homotopy; hence if MM is an H-space, then [S1,M]=:π1(M)[S^1, M] =: \pi_1(M) is abelian.

Center of a category

Variant 1

Natural transformations between functors can be composed in two different ways:

  1. If F,G,H:CDF,G,H : \mathsf{C} \to \mathsf{D} are functors and α:FG\alpha : F \to G and β:GH\beta : G \to H are natural transformations, then there is a “vertical composite” βα:FG\beta \circ \alpha : F \to G given component-wise by (βα)X=βXαX(\beta \circ \alpha)_X = \beta_X \circ \alpha_X: 2. If F1,G1:CDF_1, G_1 : \mathsf{C} \to \mathsf{D} and F2,G2:DEF_2, G_2 : \mathsf{D} \to \mathsf{E} are functors and β:F1G1\beta : F_1 \to G_1, β:F2G2\beta : F_2 \to G_2 are natural transformation, there is an horizontal composite αα\alpha * \alpha.

Vertical composition

Horizontal composition

So if one only considers natural transformations from the identity functor idC\operatorname{id}_{\mathsf{C}} to itself, one gets two different composition laws on Z(C)=End(idC)Z(\mathsf{C}) = \operatorname{End}(\operatorname{id}_{\mathsf{C}}). Again these two laws satisfy the interchange law, and thus Z(C)Z(C), called the center of the category C\mathsf{C}, is abelian. If C\mathsf{C} is a monoid seen as a category with one object, then Z(C)Z(\mathsf{C}) is the usual center of the monoid.

Variant 2

Let (C,,1)(\mathsf{C}, \otimes, 1) be a monoidal category. Then endomorphisms of the unit objects can be multiplied in two ways: the usual composition of morphisms, or a kind of convolution given by fg:111fg111f * g : 1 \cong 1 \otimes 1 \xrightarrow{f \otimes g} 1 \otimes 1 \cong 1

Then both laws are compatible (this isn’t easy to check!), and thus in a monoidal category, End(1)\operatorname{End}(1) is abelian. This implies that if an object XX in some category has nonabelian monoid of endomorphisms, then that category cannot be given a monoidal structure with XX as the unit.

Common generalization

Both variants can be generalized by looking at bicategories. If C\mathscr{C} is a bicategory and XX is an object, then the endomorphisms End(idX)\operatorname{End}(\operatorname{id}_X) of the identity of XX forms an abelian monoid, just like in variant 1.

  1. By taking C=Cat\mathscr{C} = \mathsf{Cat}, one exactly recovers variant 1;
  2. If C\mathsf{C} is a monoidal category, then its “suspension” ΣC\Sigma \mathsf{C} is a bicategory with one object; 1-morphisms are objects of C\mathsf{C}, while 2-morphisms are morphisms of C\mathsf{C}. Horizontal composition is given by tensor product of objects and vertical composition by composition in C\mathsf{C}. Then the endomorphisms of ΣC* \in \Sigma \mathsf{C} (seen as a bicategory) is exactly the center of C\mathsf{C} (seen as a monoidal category as in variant 2).

Different variant: the Drinfeld center

There exists another, completely different notion of center of a monoidal category, called the Drinfeld center (independently due to Drinfeld and Joyal–Street). It is morally the categorification of the notion of center of a monoid (a monoidal category is the same thing as a monoid in the category of categories).

Unlike everything we’ve seen so far, the Drinfeld center of a monoidal category isn’t a “commutative” (symmetric) monoidal category – it’s a braided monoidal category, something in-between a monoidal category and a symmetric monoidal category. A braided monoidal category is a monoidal category (C,)(\mathsf{C}, \otimes) equipped with a braiding, that is a natural isomorphism τX,Y:XYYX\tau_{X,Y} : X \otimes Y \to Y \otimes X satisfying some coherence equations; but unlike a symmetric monoidal category, τY,XτX,Y\tau_{Y,X} \circ \tau_{X,Y} is not the identity of XYX \otimes Y.

Given a monoidal category C\mathsf{C}, the Drinfeld center Z(C)\mathscr{Z}(\mathsf{C}) has for objects pairs (X,Φ)(X, \Phi), where XX is an object of C\mathsf{C} and Φ\Phi is a half-braiding: a natural isomorphism XXX \otimes - \to - \otimes X. Composition, tensor product and braided structure are defined in the obvious way (the unconvinced reader is encouraged to write down commutative diagrams). Then:

Theorem [Drinfeld, Joyal–Street]. The center Z(C)\mathscr{Z}(\mathsf{C}) is a braided monoidal category.

The Drinfeld center also has a completely abstract definition: it is the monoidal category of endo-2-functors of the suspension ΣC\Sigma \mathsf{C} (the 2-category with one object associated to C\mathsf{C}).

For those interested, I wrote a paper explaining how algebras on the groupoid of the Swiss-Cheese operad are “the same thing” as triples (M,N,F)(\mathsf{M}, \mathsf{N}, F) where N\mathsf{N} is a monoidal category, M\mathsf{M} is a braided monoidal category, and F:MZ(N)F : \mathsf{M} \to \mathscr{Z}(\mathsf{N}) is a braided monoidal functor. I intend to speak more about that later.

kk-fold monoidal categories

The Drinfeld center is, in many respects, the “correct” notion of center for a monoidal category – but it is not symmetric, only braided. There is some amount of commutativity lost when one goes to higher dimensional category theory. This is explained by Baez and Dolan in their article (cf. References) through kk-tuply monoidal nn-categories, an nn-category equipped with kk different “compatible” monoidal structures.

By the Eckmann–Hilton argument, all these monoidal structures are equal, but the amount of commutativity one gets changes depending on nn and kk. These types of categories eventually stabilize to a “fully symmetric” structure for k>n+1k > n + 1, as in this table (Table 21 in (Baez and Dolan)):

n=0n=0 n=1n=1 n=2n=2
k=0k=0 sets categories 2-categories
k=1k=1 monoids monoidal categories monoidal 2-categories
k=2k=2 commutative monoids braided monoidal categories braided monoidal 2-categories
k=3k=3 symmetric monoidal categories weakly involutory monoidal 2-categories
k=4k=4 strongly involutory monoidal 2-categories
k=5k=5

This Stabilization Hypothesis is one of the features that is expected of any good notion of ∞-categories, inspired by the Freudenthal suspension theorem. The notion of kk-fold monoidal categories also appears to be linked to the theory of EkE_k-operads (cf. (Balteanu et al.)), something on which I intend to speak later (cliff-hanger!).

References